Deduction versus Induction
We cannot fully understand the nature or role of inductive syllogism
in Aristotle without situating it with respect to ordinary, “deductive”
syllogism.
Aristotle’s distinction between deductive and inductive
argument is not precisely equivalent to the modern distinction.
Contemporary authors differentiate between deduction and induction in
terms of validity. (A small group of informal logicians called
“Deductivists” dispute this account.)
According to a well-worn formula,
deductive arguments are valid; inductive arguments are invalid.
The
premises in a deductive argument guarantee the truth of the conclusion:
if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. The premises in
an inductive argument provide some degree of support for the conclusion,
but it is possible to have true premises and a false conclusion.
Although some commentators attribute such views to Aristotle, this
distinction between strict logical necessity and merely probable or
plausible reasoning more easily maps onto the distinction Aristotle
makes between scientific and rhetorical reasoning (both of which we
discuss below).
Aristotle views inductive syllogism as scientific (as
opposed to rhetorical) induction and therefore as a more rigorous form
of inductive argument.
We can best understand what this amounts to by a careful comparison
of a deductive and an inductive syllogism on the same topic.
If we
reconstruct, along Aristotelian lines, a deduction on the longevity of
bileless animals, the argument would presumably run: All bileless
animals are long-lived; all men, horses, mules, and so forth, are
bileless animals; therefore, all men, horses, mules, and so forth, are
long-lived.
Defining the terms in this syllogism as: Subject Term, S=men, horses, mules, and so forth; Predicate Term, P=long-lived animals; Middle Term, M=bileless animals, we can represent this metaphysically correct inference as: Major Premise: All M are P. Minor Premise: All S are M. Conclusion:
Therefore all S are P. (Barbara.)
As we already have seen, the
corresponding induction runs: All men, horses, mules, and so forth, are
long-lived; all men, horses, mules, and so forth, are bileless animals;
therefore, all bileless animals are long-lived. Using the same
definition of terms, we are left with: Major Premise: All S are P. Minor Premise: All S are M (convertible to All M are S). Conclusion:
Therefore, all M are P. (Converted to Barbara.)
The difference
between these two inferences is the difference between deductive and
inductive argument in Aristotle.
Clearly, Aristotelian and modern treatments of these issues diverge.
As we have already indicated, in the modern formalism, one
automatically defines subject, predicate, and middle terms of a
syllogism according to their placement in the argument.
For Aristotle,
the terms in a rigorous syllogism have a metaphysical significance as
well. In our correctly formulated deductive-inductive pair, S
represents individual species and/or the individuals that make up those
species (men, horses, mules, and so forth); M represents the deep nature
of these things (bilelessness), and P represents the property that
necessarily attaches to that nature (longevity). Here then is the
fundamental difference between Aristotelian deduction and induction in a
nutshell.
In deduction, we prove that a property (P) belongs to
individual species (S) because it possesses a certain nature (M); in
induction, we prove that a property (P) belongs to a nature (M) because
it belongs to individual species (S). Expressed formally, deduction
proves that the subject term (S) is associated with a predicate term (P)
by means of the middle term (M); induction proves that the middle term
(M) is associated with the predicate term (P) by means of the subject
term (S).
Aristotle
does not claim that inductive syllogism is invalid but that the terms in
an induction have been rearranged. In deduction, the middle term joins
the two extremes (the subject and predicate terms); in induction, one
extreme, the subject term, acts as the middle term, joining the true
middle term with the other extreme. This is what Aristotle means when
he maintains that in induction one uses a subject term to argue to a
middle term.
Formally, with respect to the arrangement of terms, the
subject term becomes the “middle term” in the argument.
Aristotle distinguishes then between induction and deduction in three different ways. First, induction moves from particulars to a universal,
whereas deduction moves from a universal to particulars. The bileless
induction moves from particular species to a universal nature; the
bileless deduction moves from a universal nature to particular species.
Second, induction moves from observation to language (that is,
from sense perception to propositions), whereas deduction moves from
language to language (from propositions to a new proposition).
The
bileless induction is really a way of demonstrating how observations of
bileless animals lead to (propositional) knowledge about longevity; the
bileless deduction demonstrates how (propositional) knowledge of a
universal nature leads (propositional) knowledge about particular
species.
Third, induction identifies or explains a nature,
whereas deduction applies or demonstrates a nature. The bileless
induction provides an explanation of the nature of particular species:
it is of the nature of bileless organisms to possess a long life. The
bileless deduction applies that finding to particular species; once we
know that it is of the nature of bileless organisms to possess a long
life, we can demonstrate or put on display the property of longevity as
it pertains to particular species.
One final point needs clarification. The logical form of the
inductive syllogism, after the convertibility maneuver, is the same as
the deductive syllogism. In this sense, induction and deduction possess
the same (final) logical form.
But, of course, in order to
successfully perform an induction, one has to know that convertibility
is possible, and this requires an act of intelligence which is able to
discern the metaphysical realities between things out in the world. We
discuss this issue under non-discursive reasoning below.
No comments:
Post a Comment